|
The Marvelous and Miraculous: A Defense of Hume |
||||||||||
In the Inquiry, Hume makes a threefold distinction between demonstration, proof and probability
(I 69n; see also I 120, T 124). He does not explain demonstration, but refers to Locke and seems
to mean by it what he means by 'knowledge' in the Treatise: "assurance arising from the comparison of ideas"
(T 124). Proofs, he says are "such arguments from experience as leave no room for doubt or opposition" (I 69n).
He thinks that we have proofs in this sense for the propositions that all men die and that the sun will rise tomorrow. Since
all men have died in the past and the sun has always arisen, the evidence for these is complete, even though they are matters
of fact and could be false. In the case of probabilities, there are counter cases which cause doubt, leading us to weigh the
evidence on both sides. But in a proof it is not necessary to balance the evidence in this way. In the case of miracles, we have a
law supported by "a uniform experience." According to Hume, this means that testimony to its violation is unsupported by other
experience; if the witnesses are right, the event they attest to would be the first case in which the law has failed. Thus
we do not have to weigh the testimony against the evidence for the law; it is reasonable to reject it regardless of the credibility
of the witnesses. But if there are known violations or known cases that are analogous to them, we know that exceptions are
possible. In these cases, we have to weigh the testimony along with the evidence that the event did not happen. These events
are more or less marvelous depending on how unusual they are, but they are not miraculous. As a result, it can be reasonable
for us to accept them. 4. Hume's argument here may seem to rule out miracles
by fiat, but he thinks it is supported by our practice in evaluating evidence. In the Inquiry, he praises
the Cardinal De Retz, for instance, for thinking it is unnecessary to trace the falsity of testimony for a miracle "through
all the circumstances of knavery and credulity which produced it." Rather, Hume says, the cardinal concluded "like a just
reasoner, that such an evidence carried falsehood upon the very face of it, and that a miracle, supported by any human testimony,
was more properly a subject of derision than of argument" (I 132). Similar passages appear throughout the essay. They
are often taken to have only a rhetorical function: Hume is donning a mantle of piety by citing churchmen who have been as
skeptical as he is. But I think he has another aim. He wants to show that "just reasoners" follow the principles of testimony
he is attempting to defend in the essay, Thus, his criticism is supported by our practice in evaluating testimony and does
not simply impose an arbitrary standard. In the letter to Blair, Hume makes an even stronger claim.
He asks rhetorically: "Does a man of sense run after every silly tale of witches or hobgoblins or fairies, and canvass particularly
the evidence?" He then adds sarcastically that he never knew anyone who "examined and deliberated about nonsense" who did
not end up beieving it.14 People sometimes think Hume is just being dogmatic here, but his view is actually quite reasonable.
If a witness testifies at a trial that the defendant got past the bank guards by turning himself into a roach, the court would
not balance the chances on either side, but would consider the testimony unreliable on the face of it. In fact, the witness'
story would undermine any further evidence he might give as well. This is not dogmatic, but reasonable. It is unreasonable
on the face of it for a human to turn into an insect, since the event violates known laws. The witness is thus lying or deluded,
no matter how honest and trustworthy he has been in the past. In the language of the law, it is beyond reasonable doubt that
such events do not occur. In Campbell's defense, it must be said that Hume does not
always express the point clearly in "Of Miracles." He claims, for instance, that we should weigh the evidence on both
sides and accept the stronger. He also says that we should accept testimony to a miracle only if its falsehood would be more
miraculous that the falsehood of the fact it claims to establish (I 123-124). In these passages, he seems to equate
'miraculous' and 'improbable' despite his view that the miraculous is beyond the improbable, and so leaves himself open to
Campbell's objection. But these passages are not decisive. I will concentrate on his remak that the falsity of the testimony
must be more miraculous than the falsity of the law, since this is the crux of the argument in part I of the essay. In this part of the essay, Hume says that he will
assume that the grounds for and against the supposed miracle are both proofs. This means that the law has always been confirmed,
i.e. supported by "uniform experience," whereas the witnesses to its violation have always been reliable observers, truthful
and had good memories. On this supposition, then, "there is proof against proof, of which the strongest must prevail" (I,
122).15 Hume's argument is that we should accept the law and not the miracle, since, no matter how reliable the witnesses,
the relation between their testimony and reality is never a law. We know that witnesses make mistakes and lie, so it is possible
that these witnesses are mistaken or lying. Although their testimony is a proof "considered apart and in itself" (ibid.) it
is always defective, since there is always a reasonable doubt about it. Read in this way, Hume does not hold that here are
degrees of miracles or that miracles are just extraordinary events. We reject the testimony because its falsity is not miraculous
at all. If witnesses were never deceived, never misremembered and never lied, we might conclude that there is a law relating
testimony and reality, and hence have to weigh one miracle against another, namely, the miracle that the testimony failed
and the miracle that the law failed. But this is not the case in our world. Here the falsity of the testimony is never "more
miraculous than the fact which it endeavors to establish" (I, 123), for it is never a miracle for testimony to be mistaken.16 5. As I have interpreted him, Hume takes stories
of the miraculous to be something more than just highly improbable. This is reflected in his definition of miracles. A miracle
is a violation of a law of nature and so is not relative to evidence. More fully, he defines a miracle as "a transgression
of a law of nature by a particular volition of the Deity, or by the interposition of some invisible agent" (I 123n).
Campbell complains that this definition suggests that God is engaged in wrong-doing, i.e. he is a transgressor of the laws,
but of course Hume has no such implication in mind.18 His point is that a miracle is inconsistent with a law. The concept
of miracle is thus a metaphysical notion, if you will, and not an epistemological one. This is squarely in the theological
tradition. Aquinas, for instance, holds that "A miracle properly so called takes place when something is done outside the
order of natute."19 He does not elaborate, but it seems clear that by "the order of nature" he means natural law. His
example of a miracle is the curing of a fever "without the operation of nature." Presumably his view is that, if a child is
cured because the fever has run its course or because it was given a cool bath, i.e. because of some natural phenomenon, the
event is not a miracle; only if God intervenes with the order of nature, say because he is answering the parent's prayers,
is it a miracle. These theses follow from Hume's understanding of miracles.
First, a miracle can occur even if we have no evidence it has. Hume says that the raising of a feather a fraction of an inch
when there is no wind is as much a miracle as the raising of a house, even though we might have no suspicion that it occurred.
Such miracles are invisible while those that affect our senses are visible.20 Second, a miracle must transgress an actual
law and not just a believed one. If we mistakenly believe that L is a law, we might believe that a violation of L
is a miracle, but this would be a mistake. Events are not miracles just because they violate believed laws; they must be inconsistent
with actual laws. Finally, on Hume's account, miracles do not admit of degrees. They either violate laws and are miracles,
or they do not and are not miracles; there is no middle ground. 6. This throws light on a possible misunderstanding
about the story in the Inquiry of the Indian prince who refused to believe the European explorer's accounts of the
freezing of water. Hume thinks the prince "reasoned justly"; since he had never experienced frost or ice, it would have taken
"very strong testimony" to convince him (I 121). But Hume makes it quite clear that frost was not miraculous, but just
extraordinary (I 122n). Yet, presumably the prince believed that frost was miraculous; hence, if pressed, he
would have rejected the story as contrary to law. But this is not relevant. It is not a law that water is always
liquid just because someone believes it is. Had the prince taken it to be a law, he would have been mistaken, as a trip to
"Moscovy" (or Ottawa) in winter would have shown him. Hume would admit that it is always difficult to tell when a regularity
is a genuine law and when it is just a local phenomenon. Indeed, he is the father of such doubts. But this does not mean that laws
are just experienced regularities. To be a law, a regularity must be universal with respect to time and place, and although
violations of laws are logically possible, they are not physically possible. As a result, the prince would have been mistaken,
no matter how strongly he believed that frost violated a law. 7. In closing, I would like to consider two objections
that are often made against Hume: a. The first is that he is mistaken in thinking that we should always prefer the law over
an alleged violation, since the law itself is inductive. Suppose L is a law and e an event that violates it.
Since L is supported to degree p there is no reason in principle why the evidence for e could not be
greater than p, and hence no reason why we should not think that a miracle has occurred. The problem with this is that it confuses the issue of
whether the law statement is true with the question of whether a miracle has occurred. The defender of miracles does not just
claim that beliefs about laws may be mistaken; he is committed to holding that they are true even though events that contradict
them have occurred. We might believe that L is a law, then reject this belief because we have strong evidence that
e has occurred , but this does not show that e is a miracle. We have taken e to show that L is
not a law and never was, despite our previous evidence. To be a miracle, L must be an actual law. In the theological tradition, a miracle occurs when God
temporarily suspends the law and causes the event to occur. This is what it means for a miracle to be inconsistent with the
course of nature. To use the previous example, suppose a child recovers from a disease that always causes death. This would
be miraculous because the law is actual; it is just that it did not operate in this instance because God intervened directly
to allow the child to recover. Hume holds that we can never reasonably believe that the law holds and that the child survived
the disease. It is always more reasonable to believe that the law held even in this case than that the child had a disease
and lived. If the defender of miracles wants to claim that there is no law, well and good, but this will then imply that the
child's living was not a miracle. The fact that our evidence for the law is imperfect and that our acceptance of it
might be a mistake is thus beside the point. b. This explains another objection that is
often made to Hume. It is often argued that, if Hume is right, we cannot explain how laws come to be rejected in science.
On Hume's principle, it is never reasonable to believe that a law has been violated; thus, it is never reasonable to accept
testimony that there is experimental evidence against the law. One answer to this is that, in fact evidence against accepted
laws is not readily accepted, but has to be confirmed by other tests. But there is also a more basic problem. A scientist
who claims to have refuted a law is not claiming that a miracle has occurred, since he does not believe that the disconfirming
experiment violates a law. His view is that there never was a law; we just believed mistakenly, as it happens, that there
was. We might say that the experiment violates the law, but this is only a way of saying it is inconsistent with what we have
accepted as a law. Neither we nor the scientist want to say (i) that there is a law of nature as opposed to a believed law
and (ii) that the experiment violates this law. What would be needed to show that a miracle has occurred?
First, we would need a clear law and, second, good evidence that a violation has occurred even though nature continues to
be governed by the law, i.e. evidence that a negative instance of the law has occurred. If both these conditions are satisfied,
we have three possibilities. (1) We could accept the event and reject the law. This would be to deny that the
event is a miracle, for without the law there is no reason to think it required some special intervention by God and was not
produced by natural causes. (2) We could accept the law and reject the event. This would be to follow Hume's advice
and reject the testimony for the miracle. (3) We could accept both the law and the negative instance. As
we saw earlier, this is not a contradiction, for the religionist can argue that God merely suspended the law momentarily while
causing the event. This avoids the contradiction, but leaves the problem of showing that God intervened in this way. Since
we have no direct knowledge of his intentions, the best we can do is show that the law held before and after the event, but
this, Hume argues is evidence that the event did not occur.21 It is more plausible to think the witnesses lied
than that the law failed in just this case; for, as he says, "it is nothing strange, I hope, that men should lie in allages"
(I 127). On the one hand, we have evidence for the law that puts it past doubt, i.e. we have a proof; on the other
hand, we have the testimony that a negative instance occurred. No matter how strong the testimony, there is always a reasonable
doubt about it. Since we know that men lie, often for noble reasons to further causes they think everyone should accept,
it is possible that they are lying now. We might check their character and quiz them further, but this does not eliminate
the doubt, for even saints lie for the sake of our souls, if not for their own. The result is that it is more reasonable to
believe that the law has continued to hold through the time when the witnesses said it failed. And since this argument can
be generalized, it follows that it is never reasonable to believe in miracles. It might be thought that this is just the original balancing-of-probabilities
arguement all over again, but this is a mistake. No matter how good the evidence supporting the witnesses, we cannot eliminate
the reasonable doubt that they are lying or mistaken, whereas no one on either side has any doubt about the law being actual.
There is thus always a doubt about the testimony, but none about the law. This argument is based on rules of evidence Hume
thinks have been shown to be reliable guides in the past. They are supported by experience in a broad sense, but are not just
inductive generalizations from instances. They are deontological, if you will. They characterize the reasoning of the best
and most careful thinkers, and so help define what it is to be a reasonable thinker. These principles might lead us to make
mistakes in specific instances, but overall, Hume thinks, they will lead us to avoid more mistakes that we would make otherwise;
they also help us to discover the truth more often than not. Looked at in this way, Hume's position is much more powerful
and interesting than Campbell and Whately take it to be. It also seems to me to be the correct way of looking at the status
of principles of evidence in non-deductive logic and the theory of knowledge.22 FOOTNOTES 1. David Hume, An Inquiry Concerning
Human Understanding. ed. Charles W. Hendel (Indianapolis, Ind, 1955), p. 123. References to this edition will be given
in the text and indicated by I followed by the page number. References to the Treatise are to A Treatise
of Human Nature, ed. I. A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford, 1888) and will be given in the text as T followed by the page number. 2. George Campbell, A Dissertation
on Miracles (New York, 1983), p. 31. 3. Richard Whately, "Historic Doubts Relative
to Napoleon Buonaparte," in Essays in Philosophy, ed. Houston Peterson (New York, 1958), pp, 143-171. 4. Whately, pp. 157-158. 5. Whately, pp. 164.-165. 6. Roberet Hambourger, "Belief in Miracles
and Hume's Essay," Nous, 14 (1980), 591-593. The criticism even predates Hume's essay. See footnote 8. 7. Letters of David Hume, ed. J.
Y. T. Greig (Oxford, 1932), I, 350. 8. In defending miracles in The Analogy
of Religion, pt. II, ch. II, in 1736, Bishop Butler argued that the prior improbability of an event is no reason for doubting
its occurrence. See The Works of Joseph Butler, ed. W. E. Gladstone (Oxford, 1896), II, 216-220. As Butler put it:
"There is a presumption of millions to one, against the story of Caesar, or of any other man" (216-217). 9. David Hume: Philosophical Historian,
ed. D. F. Norton and R. H. Popkin (Indianapolis, Ind., 1965), p 128. 10. Ibid. 11. There is also a suggestion of the argument
against miracles (as I interpret it) in the Treatise. In book II, iii, 1, Hume says that if a traveler claimed he had
seen fruits ripen in the winter in a climate of 50 degrees north latitude, "he would find few so credulous as to believe him"
(T 402-403). He then claims that the traveler would find the same reaction, if he said that he had visited a country
where the inhabitants have the same character as those in Plato's Republic or in Hobbes' Leviathan. His point
is that "There is a general course of nature in human actions, as well as in the operations of the sun and the climate." Hume
does not mention miracles in this passage, but in the comparable passage in the Inquiry he says that, if a traveler
reported a people "entirely divested of avarice, ambition, or revenge," we would "prove him a liar with the same certainty
as if he had stuffed his narration with stories of centaurs and dragons, miracles and prodigies" (I 94). 12. Dissertation. p. 98 13. Ibid. 14. Ibid. Compare the more muted passage on
I 128: "Fools are industrious in propagating the imposture, while the wise and learned are contented, in general,
to deride its absurdity, without informing themselves of the particular facts by which it may be distinctly refuted." 15. In his remarks about the notion of proof
in the letter to Blair, Hume says that "there are degrees of this species, and when a weaker proof is opposed by a stronger,
it is overcome." Letters. I, 350. 16. The argument in part I of "Of Miracles"
is often taken to be a priori, while the arguments in part II are a posteriori. See R. M. Burns, The Great Debate on Miracles:
From Joseph Glanvill to David Hume (Lewisburg, Pa., 1981), pp. 142 ff., esp. 142-143, 153-154, 158-159. If my interpretation
is correct, this is mistaken. An a priori argument does not rest on any empirical premisses or assumptions, but Hume's argument
rests on the premiss that what witnesses say is sometimes false. The confusion arises, I think, because Hume holds that the
argument in part I is sound regardless of the specific testimony for the miracle. Hence we do not have to investigate this
evidence, but know beforehand that it is weaker than the evidence for the law. This makes the argument appear a priori, even
though it is not. 17. Leibniz thinks that everything happens according
to the divine plan, but distinguishes between "subordinate maxims" and "the most general of God's laws." The former are natural
laws because they govern "the nature of things"; the latter are God's general intentions. Miracles, he says, violate the subordinate
maxims but not the most general laws. G. W. Leibnez, Discourse on Metaphysics section 7, in Philosophical Essays,
tr. Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber (Indianapolis, 1989), p. 40. When Hume says that miracles violate laws of nature, he has
in mind these subordinate maxims. As he makes clear in section XI of the first Inquiry, he thinks we have no evidence
of God's overall intentions. 18. Dissertation, p. 59n. 19. Summa Theologica, I, qu. 110, art.4,
The Basic Writings of St. Thomas Aquinas, ed. Anton C. Pegis (New York, 1945, 1, 1022. 20. The distinction between visible and invisible
miracles is found in Butler. He holds that the incarnation of Jesus and the revelation of truths in the Bible are invisible
miracles, since they are not "a proof of a divine mission," Analogy of Religion, pt. II ch. ii, see Works, II,
213. A visible miracle, on the other hand, is one that falls within our experience and so can act as a sign to guide the faithful,
in particular, to prove the invisible ones. Both types are outside the course of nature in Aquinas' sense, since they result
from God's direct intervention rather than from natural law. 21. That we have no evidence of God's intentions
is the topic of section XI, "Of a Particular Providence and of a Future State." 22. An earlier version of this paper was read
at the College of St. Rose, Albany. I would like to thank the audience for comments that helped form the final version. I
would also like to thank Michael Smithurst who commented on the paper at the 20th Hume Conference in Ottawa (1994) and members
of the audience who encouraged me to develop the argument further.
|
||||||||||
|
|
|